Introduction
In Herczegfalvy v Austria the
European Court of Human Rights ruled that imposed psychiatric treatment without
consent did not breach Article 3 of the European Convention of Human Rights (freedom
from torture and inhuman or degrading treatment) in situations of medical
or therapeutic necessity (Bartlett, 2011: p.
525). In order to grant this warrant to override the usual ethical position
of respecting patient autonomy it is necessary to define what medical or
therapeutic necessity is. Bartlett, a legal expert, suggested therapeutic
necessity should involve “treating the underlying disorder or improving
outcomes” in situations of severity (Bartlett, 2011: p. 525) whilst expressing
scepticism about psychiatric treatments.
I will argue that Bartlett’s criteria are unnecessarily
restrictive as to what a therapeutic objective is (for example can
include reducing distress), is overly pessimistic about psychiatric treatment
effectiveness, that necessity involves the clinician weighing up several
factors and that safeguards exist to oversee clinical decision-making.
1.
Why is Therapeutic Necessity Important?
“A characteristic feature of mental health
legislation … is the provision which is made for waiving, in certain cases,
that respect for patients’ autonomy, their right not to be treated without
their explicit consent, … regarded as a requirement in most fields of medicine.”
(Mathews, 2000: p.59)
Psychiatric detention and treatment without consent may
be regarded by some as breaching Articles 3 (freedom for torture and inhuman/
degrading treatment), 5 (liberty and
security of the person) and 8 (respect for private and family life) of the
European Convention of Human Rights (Bartlett, 2012: 352). On the specific issue of enforced
treatment without consent the case of Herczegfalvy
v Austria is “key” in establishing under which circumstances Article 3 has
not been breached (Bartlett, 2011).
“The established principles of
medicine are admittedly in principle decisive
in such cases; as a general
rule, a measure which is a therapeutic
necessity cannot be regarded
as inhuman or degrading. The Court must
nevertheless satisfy itself
that the medical necessity has been convincingly
shown to exist.” (Bartlett, 2012: p.365)
Specific advice has been given firstly for necessity (Article 18) and what
constitutes therapeutic (Article 19).
“The Recommendation of the
Committee of Ministers to Member States concerning the protection of the
human rights and dignity of persons with mental disorder, Rec(2004)10,.. sets
out different criteria for involuntary treatment and involuntary detention. The
substantive recommendations concerning involuntary treatment are as follows:
Article 18 – Criteria for involuntary treatment A person may be subject to
involuntary treatment only if all the following conditions are met: i. the
person has a mental disorder; ii. the person’s condition represents a
significant risk of serious harm to his or her health or to other persons; iii.
no less intrusive means of providing appropriate care are available; iv. the
opinion of the person concerned has been taken into consideration. Article 19 –
Principles concerning involuntary treatment 1. Involuntary treatment should: i.
address specific clinical signs and symptoms; ii. be
proportionate to the person’s state of health; iii. form part of a written
treatment plan; iv. be documented; v. where appropriate, aim to enable the use
of treatment acceptable to the person as soon as possible.” (Bartlett, 2012: p.374)
Legal justification for enforced psychiatric treatment
without consent relies on the condition of therapeutic
necessity and split into
two further conditions – what is therapeutic
intervention and what is necessity.
2. What is Bartlett’s definition of Therapeutic
Necessity?
Bartlett, a legal academic, defines therapeutic (as
opposed to therapeutically necessary) as “treatments {which} may appropriately
be prescribed which are not therapeutically necessary. Treatments which attack
the symptoms of a disorder but not the underlying disease are an obvious
example” (Bartlett, 2011: p. 533) as well as “treating the underlying disorder
or improving outcomes” (Bartlett, 2011: p. 531). The Code of Practice of the
Mental Health Act (1983) requires that appropriate treatment “must be treatment
which is for the purpose of alleviating or preventing a worsening of the
patient’s mental disorder or its symptoms or manifestations” (Bartlett, 2011:
p.533). Whereas Bartlett does not regard lessening symptoms as part of therapeutic
necessity – only those treatments that target “underlying disease” or
improve outcomes (but not outcomes such as improving symptoms). Bartlett
further distinguishes between therapeutic appropriateness and
therapeutic necessity with only the latter justifying compulsion (Bartlett,
2011: p.534). To discuss this distinction further:
“that an appropriate treatment is available should
not mean that a State should… force people to undergo that treatment. ‘Medical necessity’ as intended by the Court
presumably does not mean that without such treatment the patient will suffer
death or serious physical injury, since, at least as regards the neuroleptic
medication, it is not obvious that this would have been the result in Herczegfalvy.
The degree to which treatment can be
enforced in order to safeguard others in society is likely to prove a
controversial point” (Bartlett, 2012 p.366).
Bartlett sets further requirements for therapeutic
necessity:
“likelihood of
given result… achieve long-term and sustainable change in … underlying
disorder…some sort of substantive threshold of degree of
benefit… {when} stabilization of a condition that would otherwise worsen
may sometimes be all that is realistic, it is possible… that treatments that
will reliably achieve this end might …meet… therapeutic necessity test; but the
outcomes of treatment over non-treatment must presumably be real, significant
and manifest” (Bartlett, 2011: p. 534).
“Is the degree of likelihood of success relevant–that
is, even to prevent death, can it be said that a highly intrusive and painful
treatment with a low probability of success is ‘medically necessary’? These and
many other questions are left unanswered by the standard articulated… While the
treating physician may be best placed to make an initial evaluation of the
situation.. he or she is too close to the situation for the process to end with
him or her…the State’s right to impose treatment raises a variety of political,
legal and social issues as well as medical ones. This is not a purely medical
matter, and the process must allow for an independent review of the decision” (Bartlett, 2012: p.367).
Bartlett’s own conclusions on psychiatric treatment are that
they do not meet his ideal of knowing based on the patient’s own history of a
treatment that has a high degree of success with few adverse effects but that in
practice
“serious
mental illness involve a considerable amount of trial and error by clinicians
in individual cases…results of this process can be mixed: sometimes, drug
combinations are found which largely alleviate the disorder with minimal
adverse effects; sometimes drug treatments have minimal beneficial effects,
following considerable unpleasant adverse effects. In these circumstances,
knowledge of probable outcomes in the specific case may be low, and the above standard
would not allow compulsory treatment to be used” (Bartlett, 2011: p. 534)
Further,
“reasonable certainty of diagnosis, therapeutically
necessary treatment, and outcome should be required before involuntary
treatment is contemplated. If such certainty is absent, it is difficult to see
that a human rights infringement is ‘balanced’ by a corresponding benefit (if
indeed such a balancing is the correct approach), since the benefit is
speculative. The requirement that a therapeutic necessity must be ‘convincingly
shown to exist’, as required by Herczegfalvy, suggests a medical consensus on
the appropriate treatment in the patient’s case, and disagreements between
medical professionals are thus particularly problematic” (Bartlett, 2011: p.535).
Summarising Bartlett’s view
is the difference between a treatment being appropriate (such as being
indicated for a condition) or available and therapeutic necessity. He
does not outline what the grounds for necessity are but does seem to
acknowledge it is not necessarily life or death severity but even preventing
harm to others is potentially controversial (Bartlett, 2012 p.366). Bartlett
expects that to meet therapeutic necessity threshold to justify
compulsion that proposed treatments should have a known high probability of affecting
the underlying causes of disorder and achieving a substantial clinical benefit
(Bartlett, 2011: p. 534). Taking into account the realities of clinical
practice in psychiatry as well as adverse effects in treatment Bartlett doubts
that psychiatric treatments would meet this threshold (Bartlett, 2011: p. 534
and p. 535) and that independent review of treatment plans by clinicians is
necessary when compulsion is used (Bartlett, 2012 p.367).
3. Problems with Bartlett’s interpretation
of Therapeutic Necessity
There are several problems with Bartlett’s positions –
medical treatment in all of medicine does not necessarily have to address the
underlying causes of a disorder to be regarded as therapeutic, psychiatric
treatments overlap in effectiveness with many general medical treatments
regarded as effective, in general medicine as well as psychiatry treatment
often involves uncertainty of outcome, adverse effects are common to all types
of medical treatment not just psychiatric treatment, his views on what is necessity
may be regarded as overly restrictive to clinicians and finally his values seem
to be against psychiatric treatment which may have informed his criteria for therapeutic
necessity. I shall start with discussions of what is regarded as therapeutic
in medicine before moving onto necessity.
Critical psychiatrists offer two models of prescribing goals
– one a “disease-centred model” where medication reverses hypothesised
mechanisms of disease producing symptoms -similar to Bartlett’s definition of therapeutic
- or a “drug-centred model” where a drug is regarded as always harmful and
producing many effects of which some may be regarded by the patient as
beneficial such as blunting of painful emotions (Yeomans et al, 2015) – which
would not meet Bartlett’s criteria. A more sophisticated view of therapeutic
interventions in psychiatry has three potential goals: “alleviation of symptoms
without affecting the disease course; prevention of progression, but not
curative …; and curative or preventive …” (Lieberman et al, 2019: p.794
Sackett - the prime mover behind the “Evidence Based
Medicine movement” - along with his co-authors outlined a list of objectives of
treatments (Sackett et al, 1991: p. 189) which are relevant to discussions of therapeutic
intentions in general medicine as whole as well as psychiatry in
particular. Cure as an objective should be applied to circumstances such as a
reversal of disease process but in layman terms often refers to situations
where the symptoms are eliminated or a disease mechanism is compensated for
(such as insulin to replace the body’s own insulin or benzodiazepines are used
to greatly reduce the symptoms of alcohol withdrawal). Prevent recurrence
refers to situations where treatment is aimed at preventing a return of the
medical condition (or maintenance antipsychotics in schizophrenia) and can be expanded
to preventing a first occurrence of a condition (such as vaccination to prevent
infections) (Huda, 2019: p.80). Limiting deterioration are where interventions
are given to prevent further problems such as the use of plasters and surgical
fixation to prevent displacement of fractures or skills training to prevent
loss of psychosocial functioning in severe mental illness. Many medical
conditions are treated to prevent known complications associated with the
condition such as the use of antihypertensives in high blood pressure to
prevent cardiovascular disease. Relieving distress or symptoms is an important
therapeutic goal as it is often distress or other unpleasant experiences
labelled as symptoms that bring people to seek out medical help. Examples
include painkillers for pain or antidepressants in depression.
These therapeutic goals regarded as legitimate in
medicine as a whole and applied to psychiatry in particular are clearly broader
than the narrow definition of Bartlett of affecting the underlying cause of the
disorder. It should also be noted at this point that treatments used in general
medicine do not always affect the underlying cause of the disorder either
(Huda, 2019: p.291-292). Although outcomes such as preventing suicide and
homicide may be accepted as outcomes by Bartlett they are thankfully relatively
infrequent so it is difficult to have studies large enough to demonstrate
proven benefit in achieving these outcomes. This should not be used as a reason
to rule out psychiatric treatment unless that is one’s intention a priori as
other treatment goals are regarded as legitimate in medicine.
In terms of establishing “substantive
threshold of degree of benefit”(Bartlett, 2011: p.534) for psychiatric
treatments, there is an overlap in effectiveness between medication used in
psychiatry and general medicine in achieving therapeutic objectives (Leucht et
al, 2012 and Leucht et al, 2015). What is the threshold in establishing
substantial benefit? The psychiatric treatment with the largest effectiveness
magnitude is electroconvulsive therapy (Huda, 2019: p.284) so if a threshold
for substantial benefit is set that excludes antidepressants, antipsychotics
and mood stabilisers then the only treatment option left under Bartlett’s
criteria for enforced treatment would be electroconvulsive therapy – surely a
drastic conclusion and potentially harmful when the excluded treatments may be more
appropriate choices for the particular patient.
Bartlett’s point about trial
and error in deciding treatments also applies in general medicine given the
overlap in effectiveness with psychiatric and general medical treatments. There
is often no absolute certainty about treatment in general medicine either.
Number Needed to Treat (NNT) is a metric used in the medical literature: it
indicates how many people need to be treated with the specified treatment
before one person achieves the target significant clinical benefit compared to
those given placebo or other control treatment. The NNT for psychiatric
treatments overlaps with those of treatments regarded as effective in general
medicine (Huda, 2019: p. 285-286). This suggests that there is a similar degree
of therapeutic uncertainty in general medicine and psychiatry. As for certainty
of diagnosis, there are similar degrees of diagnostic agreement in psychiatry
compared to general medicine (Huda, 2019: p.120-143). Finally, problematic
adverse effects are frequently found in treatments used in general medicine
(Huda, 2019: 288-289). One argument that could be used by Bartlett is that he
is discussing enforced treatments not treatments in everyday practice but the comparison
presented here is relevant – that treatments in psychiatry are similar
in some important respects to those used in general medicine and fulfil therapeutic
criteria. The question of whether they should be enforced then rests on the necessity.
An article by Curtice summarised several of the crucial
issues when it comes to necessity:
“Margin of appreciation …clinical
decisions that are proportional, therapeutically necessary and in keeping with
accepted clinical practice are very unlikely to be outside this margin…
Proportionality Clinical
intervention needs to balance the severity of the effect of the intervention
with the severity of the presenting clinical problem, i.e. be a proportionate
response to a clinical scenario.
Threshold of severity to
engage Article 3 Ill-treatment must attain a minimum level of severity;
assessment of this minimum is relative. ...” (Curtice,
2008: p. 390)
The concept of necessity requires
balancing several factors to demonstrate that the therapeutic intervention is
“proportionate response to a clinical scenario” (Curtice, 2008: p.390). These
factors include “severity” of the problem (degree of symptoms, degree of
impairment and probability of improvement if no treatment is offered as well as
probability and nature of consequent risks) and “severity” of proposed
treatment (the nature of the treatment, the probability and nature of adverse
effects). There is also the question of probability of the treatment being
effective but this also needs balanced with the consequences of not treating
the problem – the worse the prognosis the more likely a low chance of success
would be regarded as justified by necessity. Examples from clinical
practice are now discussed.
An elated manic patient may wish to continue in this state
(though there are often periods of mixed moods including depressed mood) and
not see any problem with spending large amounts of money or reckless impulsive
decisions that may cause problems such as sexual activity with people other
than their spouse. The clinician may decide that the priority is to reduce the
manic symptoms which should also have the benefit of preventing complications
in the person’s life by their disinhibited behaviour. (One patient told me “you
spoilt my fun” when I had reduced their manic symptoms). A depressed patient
who is suicidal may not agree with the doctor for starting treatment with the
therapeutic goal of reducing symptoms and preventing occurrence of suicide:
they may believe they deserve to suffer and die because of guilt, they may
think treatment is pointless because of depressive pessimism, they may
prioritise harm avoidance of treatment side-effects A patient with what the
doctor regards as delusions or hallucinations may believe in the truth of what
the doctor describes as psychotic symptoms. They may want to have any
associated distress reduced but in consonant with their beliefs/ hallucinations
(such as the persecution ending from persecutors). Apart from reducing distress
the doctor may wish to prevent the occurrence of events – such as self-harm or
aggression- that may be associated with the psychosis.
Weighing up the potential harms with treatment with the
consequent risks of not treating is easier for certain risks – if the patient
is a higher risk to others or self and harder for others – such as for
continued presence of what seems mild-moderate distress or impaired
functioning. Deciding on necessity depends on how one values these
different factors. Sometimes the conclusion of weighing up these factors is
that no treatment is indicated. This type of weighing up these factors is the
heart of clinical practice with the additional complication of over-riding
autonomy. Although Bartlett expresses
the view that decisions about enforced treatment are more than medical
decisions (Bartlett, 2012: p.367) these decisions take place within the context
of a legal framework with limits on medical decision-making, often with
guidance such as the Code of Practice in England and Wales to provide the
principles that should guide the values used to underpin decision-making with supervisory procedures such as appeals and
Tribunals to oversee the use if compulsory treatments. Bartlett focusses on the
right of autonomy but ignores other rights such as the right to life.
Bartlett’s own values are at
a minimum highly sceptical about psychiatric treatments. He puts forwards his
own view that “benefits of psychiatric medication are not necessarily
clear-cut, and the risks can be significant” (Bartlett, 2011: p.517) despite
the overlap in effectiveness and adverse effects with treatments used in
general medicine as discussed above. Contrary to his own claim to want a
“balanced reflection” (Bartlett 2011; p. 517) barely mentions any benefits but
instead discusses at length adverse effects including a claim that
antipsychotics kills more people that it saves which is contradicted by the
research evidence that antipsychotics reduce mortality (Tiihonen et al, 2009).
This illustrates the perils of relying on balanced accurate evidence from
someone advocating a legal argument.
Bartlett describes
psychiatric medication as “mind-altering drugs” (Bartlett,
2011: p.535) – a highly value-laden term that makes the medication sound
frightening but just highlights conceptual confusion. After all, psychiatric
medication is used to benefit people with mental health conditions whom are
regarded as having unpleasant, distressing or impaired functioning of mind–
hence the therapeutic aim would to be alter the state of mind in a beneficial
way surely? Which begs the question what does Bartlett think psychiatric
treatment should alter? The feet? These values may inform Bartlett’s views that
only reversing the underlying causes of the condition or better (unspecified)
outcomes but not reducing symptoms should be regarded as valid therapeutic
necessity to justify enforced treatment. However, given most psychiatric
treatments are justified on clinical grounds for reducing symptoms and does not
reverse underlying mechanisms of mental disorders (many of which are unknown)
(see discussion above) Bartlett’s proposals -perhaps influenced by his values
towards psychiatric treatment - would rule out of bounds most psychiatric
treatments as fulfilling therapeutic necessity criteria.
Therapeutic objectives
apart from affecting underlying causes pf disorder or preventing outcomes –
such as reducing distress or limiting deterioration – are regarded as
legitimate in general medical practice. Psychiatric treatments overlap in
effectiveness with treatments in general medicine and setting too high a
threshold to justify enforced treatment would leave only electroconvulsive
therapy as the only compulsory treatment option. Uncertainty of treatment
response also occurs in general medicine. Necessity involves a balancing
of the likelihood and nature of benefits and harms of proposed treatment versus
the likely outcomes and risks of the patient’s clinical state. There are
various laws, guidance and supervisory procedures to oversee the medical
decision making. Bartlett’s statements on psychiatric treatments suggest his
values are against medication which influence his criteria for therapeutic
necessity.
4. Conclusion
Bartlett set out restrictive criteria for therapeutic
necessity over-riding autonomy and justifying enforced treatment for mental
disorder – affecting underlying causes of the disorder and /or affecting
outcomes apart from reducing symptoms as well as requiring lack of uncertainty
over benefits and expressed scepticism over psychiatric treatment in terms of
effectiveness and adverse effects. He argued these are not solely medical
decisions.
I argued therapeutic necessity is a conjunction of
two terms – what is therapeutic and what is necessity. Therapeutic
involves a broad series of potential therapeutic goals such as preventing
occurrence of negatively perceived outcomes or relieving distress (Sackett et
al, 1991: 189) rather than Bartlett’s narrow definition. Psychiatric treatments
are in many ways similar to treatments in general medicine in terms of
effectiveness, uncertainty over benefit and propensity to adverse effects.
Bartlett’s scepticism over psychiatric treatments seem to be underpinned by
values biased against psychiatric medication. Necessity involves
judgements by clinicians as to the current severity and risk of adverse
outcomes of the patient’s current clinical situation and that of the proposed
treatment. These judgments and actions by clinicians are limited by statute
with guidance on how to implement the laws and supervision of clinical practice
for example by review tribunals.
References
Bartlett, P., 2011. ‘The necessity must be convincingly shown to
exist’: Standards for compulsory treatment for mental disorder under the Mental
Health Act 1983. Medical law review, 19(4), pp.514-547.
Bartlett, P., 2012. Chapter 14 Rethinking Herczegfalvy: the Convention
and the control of psychiatric treatment in Brems, E. ed., 2012. Diversity
and European human rights: rewriting judgments of the ECHR. Cambridge
University Press.
Bloch, S.E. and Chodoff, P.E., 1991. Psychiatric ethics.
Oxford University Press
Curtice, M., 2008. Article 3 of the Human
Rights Act 1998: implications for clinical practice. Advances in
Psychiatric Treatment, 14(5), pp.389-397.
Emanuel, E.J. and Emanuel, L.L., 1992. Four
models of the physician-patient relationship. Jama, 267(16),
pp.2221-2226
Fulford, K.W.M., Smirnov, A.Y.U. and Snow, E., 1993. Concepts of
disease and the abuse of psychiatry in the USSR. The British Journal of
Psychiatry, 162(6), pp.801-810
Hope, T., 2004. A very short introduction to medical ethics.Oxford
University Press, Oxford
Huda, A.S., 2019. The Medical Model in Mental Health: An
Explanation and Evaluation. Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Lieberman, J.A., Small, S.A. and Girgis, R.R., 2019. Early detection
and preventive intervention in schizophrenia: from fantasy to reality. American
Journal of Psychiatry, 176, pp.794-810
Leucht, S., Hierl, S., Kissling, W., Dold, M. and Davis, J.M., 2012.
Putting the efficacy of psychiatric and general medicine medication into
perspective: review of meta-analyses. The British Journal of Psychiatry, 200(2),
pp.97-106.
Leucht, S., Helfer, B., Gartlehner, G. and Davis, J.M., 2015. How
effective are common medications: a perspective based on meta-analyses of major
drugs. BMC medicine, 13(1), p.253.
Matthews, E., 2000. Autonomy and the psychiatric patient. Journal
of applied philosophy, pp.59-70.
Sackett D.L., Haynes R.B., Guyatt G.H. & Tugwell P., 1991 Clinical
Epidemiology: A Basic Science for Clinical Medicine (Second Edition)
Boston/Toronto/London. Little, Brown and Company
Tiihonen, J., Lönnqvist, J., Wahlbeck, K., Klaukka, T., Niskanen, L.,
Tanskanen, A. and Haukka, J., 2009. 11-year follow-up of mortality in patients
with schizophrenia: a population-based cohort study (FIN11 study). The
Lancet, 374(9690), pp.620-627.
Yeomans, D., Moncrieff, J. and Huws, R., 2015. Drug-centred
psychopharmacology: a non-diagnostic framework for drug treatment. BJPsych
Advances, 21(4), pp.229-236.